ORDERED SURVEYS OF ARGUMENTS ON AN ISSUE
(Pro-aut-contra surveys)
The purpose of making argument
surveys on an issue is both semantical and logical. A survey is a set
of arguments for and against an issue all of which are explicitly expressed
as separate statements. (Surveys are almost always written). This
has the semantical advantage of clarity. Issues and arguments that are
insufficiently precise, too inconcise or inappropriately-expressed will
exhibit these weaknesses more readily when separately stated. The logical
advantage of surveys is chiefly that the relations of implication, relevance
or irrelevance between the issue and the arguments and between the various
arguments themselves can be more easily examined and readily grasped as
a whole.
The function of an ordered
survey is not always to prove or disprove the issue, since genuine issues
can normally be resolved only in practice and depend upon the achievement
of the consensus of the parties involved. There can be both highly-relevant
and tenable arguments for, as well as against, an issue so that no rational
conclusion as to the whole can be derived. If a conclusion is reached
it is not a logically-valid one in the strict sense because it is an evaluation as to which side presents the strongest arguments
when all are taken together and compared.
Making a preliminary survey
Few people without training and experience in debating or scientific
argumentation are at the outset capable of making a complete and ordered
survey of consistent, clear and relevant arguments for and against any
particular issue. Therefore, it is usual to make a preliminary survey
of the issue and arguments. This can serve as the basis for a fuller
survey where the arguments are ordered according to certain rules. One
may even start with a text or recorded materials upon which the survey
is to be based. The following exemplifies this:
"In our opinion world security is threatened by nuclear power plants. Consider the cases of India, Israel, Pakistan and South Africa. Nuclear power plants have provided the technology they require to make them capable of developing nuclear weapons. Further, fissionable products can more easily be stolen for illegal uses when nuclear power plants exist, even though official authorities claim their security systems to be almost infallible. Obviously, no system where the human factor is involved is ever infallible. It's no use arguing that nuclear technology is under the control of expert scientists because this is not so and because scientists do not own the technology or its products."
The underlined is clearly what constitutes the issue-statement (hereafter I0) and it is a descriptive statement. The arguments for and against will therefore be ordered as statements that support or weaken the tenability of 10, making those that are directly relevant to the issue main arguments (hereafter 'first-order arguments'), and those that are directly related to a main argument sub-arguments.
Arguments that are first-order
are indicated by capital P for pro and C for contra and are numbered
for the sake of identification (i.e. the numbering does not indicate
importance or precedence). Further, arguments that do not relate directly
to the issue but instead refer to a first-order argument (whether pro
or contra the issue) are sub- arguments. Sub-arguments are thus indirectly
related to the issue, through the first-order argument to which they
refer.
Sub-arguments can be of any order from second-order and onwards numerically.
There can be any number of sub-arguments for or against any main argument,
whatever their order.
For example, p1P1, p2P1, p5P1 / c1P1, c2P1, c3P1 / and p1C1, p2C1 would
all symbolise second-order arguments. The second-order argument p1P2
' supports £2 and therefore indirectly supports the issue-statement.
However c1P2 indirectly weakens the issue-statement, as would p1C1.
An argument labelled c1C1 will therefore be in indirect support of the
issue-statement.
Third-order arguments relate directly to the preceding second-order
argument. Thus, the triple symbol pair c1c1P1 is an argument against
c1P1, thus also in support of P1 and of the issue-statement.
Further, c2c1P1 would be another argument against c1P1 (not necessarily
more important than c1c1P1, as the numbers are for identification only
and do not represent order of priority of the arguments of that order).
Fourth-order arguments would be indicated by four symbol pairs as c1c1c1P1
and so on.
Following the above method of label-ordering, the example text above
can be ordered as a survey to demonstrate the relations of its arguments
as follows;-
I0 World security is threatened by nuclear power plants
P1 because they provide the technology required to make countries
capable of developing nuclear weapons
p1P1 Consider the cases of India, Israel, Pakistan and South
Africa
P2 because fissionable products can more easily be stolen for
illegal uses
c1P2 but official authorities claim their security systems to
be almost infallible
c1c1P2 but no system where the human factor is involved is ever
infallible
C1 No, because nuclear
technology is under the control of expert scientists.
c1C1 but scientists do not own the technology or its products
The above obviously does
not exhaust the issue, but it serves to show how three main lines of
argument (headed by P1, P2 and C1) are related to the issue and their
sub-arguments. There is no way to decide when an issue is exhausted
as this depends upon experience, imagination and knowledge of the facts
pertinent to the issue. Despite this, however, certain arguments can
be so tenable and relevant and of such a degree of irrefutability that
they serve to make only one conclusion likely, even though the survey
is not exhaustive of all main arguments possible. They are not thereby
logically irrefutable, but practically so in that their denial leads
to absurd standpoints.
To judge whether any survey is sufficiently ordered we need to apply
the following standards, which apply equally to surveys with descriptive
and prescriptive issue-statements.
Rule 1) The arguments
must be formulated explicitly enough to enable one to decide whether
they are Pro or contra. If a statement could equally well figure as
pro or contra, it is not a sufficiently clear descriptive argument.
(The main arguments must be ordered correctly as for (P1, P2, P3 etc.)
or against (C1, C2, C3 etc) the issue-statement, see example above).
The exact wording of an argument is important, so the semantical standards
of clarity, conciseness and precision should be observed. Unclear arguments
can frequently be improved by reformulation of their expressions according
to the principles earlier stated.
Rule 2) All arguments that are of a sub-order should be labelled
so as to indicate to which main arguments they are related and whether
they are pro or contra the argument to which they directly relate.
(The example already given above shows c1P2 is a second-order argument
against P2, which is for 10, and therefore is indirectly against I0.
Then c1c1P2 is a third-order argument, being against c1P2 and thus indirectly
for I0). The purpose in labeling is semantical and also in the interests
of the economy of thought. A clear overview of a complex issue is best
attained by the systematic ordering of an argument-survey. This process
facilitates the subsequent process of evaluation of the arguments on
the whole and the eventual drawing of a conclusion as to the relative
strength of the issue-statement.
Rule 3) No argument
that is directly or indirectly in support of the issue-statement may
contradict any other supporting arguments, whatever order they may be.
Contrariwise, no arguments directly or indirectly against the issue-statement
should contradict one another whatever order they be.
If so the argumentation is incompatible and the survey must be altered
to remove this. This rule is an application of the principle of non-contradiction
(see section one of this book). Its purpose is to bring overall logical
consistency to all the arguments that can be forwarded either for or
against an issue-statement. Evidently, pro-arguments can legitimately
contradict contra-arguments of the same order. In such a case one can
only decide between them on the strength of the relative sub-arguments.
It is important to note that sub-arguments which indirectly support
an issue-statement can be ordered on either 'side' of a survey, depending
upon which relation they bear to the main argument. See as follows;
I0 'In Scandinavian nations party politicians are bound to vote according to officially-adopted party conference policies.'
PRO CONTRA
PI because those who do not are not put up by their parties for re-election.
C1 but this does not occur in every instance
c1C1 but those who do not are not put up by their parties for re-election.
We see here that P1 also could figure as c1C1. It is a matter of choice
where the argument is placed, for its evaluation will not be affected.
If the argument is regarded as of great weight, however, it is evidently
better to formulate it as a first-order argument (than as a second-order
argument on the opposite 'side' of a survey).
Rule 4) Implicit assertions supporting the issue-statement
should not contradict any stated arguments which also support the issue-statement
(directly/or indirectly).
Likewise, implicit assertions that are against the issue-statement should
not contradict any stated arguments which are also against the issue-statement
(directly or indirectly).
This rule is necessary in that most arguments on general issues are
based upon assumptions. The complete grounds for any general argument
cannot normally be made explicit in full. If the grounds assumed are
likely to be in conflict with other arguments that they would be in
support of, they should be made explicit as argument-expressions and
rule 3 applied to see whether contradiction arises.
For example, in continuance of the example above under rule 3:-
Suppose that some contra-argument C1 is based on the assumption that
'there are instances where the party parliamentary group decide that
the issue to be voted on is purely a matter of individual moral conscience,
such as the issues of capital punishment or right to abortion'. This
assumption would not be logically consistent with the contra-argument
C2:-
C2 but parliamentary representatives of a party may only abstain from voting unless they receive directions from official party conference policies.
Impracticable and untrue
as C2 is as an argument, it is not consistent with the assumption upon
which C1 was supposedly based. One cannot both abstain from voting and
vote on grounds of Individual moral conscience etc. (C2 is also not
clearly a contra-argument, as it stands without further explanation).
Application of the rules
Applying these standards
to the example about nuclear power plants it can be seen from the original
text that the writer-is arguing for the issue-statement, so P1 is correctly
labeled. However, considering whether P1 could just as well have been
labeled C1, we find that those who see it as a benefit that countries
with nuclear power plants should be capable of developing nuclear weapons
would indeed label the argument as contra the issue-statement. According
to rule 1 therefore the argument is not sufficiently clear. That is
not clear about it when taken outside the textual context is that it
assumes implicitly that it is an undesirable state of affairs that certain
countries are capable of developing nuclear weapons. The argument could
therefore be further qualified as follows:-
P1 because they provide the technology required to make countries
capable of developing undesirable nuclear weapons.
The debate about desirability or undesirability would then become relegated to the second-order argumentation, if such a point is regarded as debatable.
Secondly, the sub-argument p1P1 is correctly labeled as a statement supporting P1.
The third rule requires that we ensure no contradictions between P1, p1P1, P2, c1c1P2 and c1c1 occur, because all of these are statements in support of the issue-statement, either directly or indirectly. In this case there is compatibility in that all of these statements could be tenable at once.
Rule 4 does not appear to
be infringed in the example, though this does not guarantee that it
is fully observed. Further analysis may bring to light assumptions that
are not justifiable.
Evaluation of the arguments
Evaluation requires three assessments. Firstly the tenability and secondly the relevance of each main argument is assessed, where necessary by also assessing the tenability and relevance of the supporting and weakening sub-arguments. Lastly, the main arguments, as assessed for tenability and relevance, are reviewed together and compared as to their relative strength pro and contra. This may lead one to a conclusion, based on all the arguments and only those arguments (i.e. excluding 'after-thought' arguments not included in the survey). The conclusion may be for the issue-statement, against it or a 'stalemate', where neither side has an overweight and one therefore reserves judgement. In some cases of course, no conclusion will be arrived at due either to incompleteness of a survey, either as to arguments that ought to have been included or as to lacking information regarding the tenability of main arguments. However, all arguments end somewhere.
Applying the above to the
argument example about nuclear power plants, I make an evaluation for
purposes of demonstration, it being based upon my own information and
judgement at present, (i.e. the correctness of my information and judgement
is not thereby entirely guarantee:-
P1 is greatly strengthened by p1P1, India having exploded nuclear weapons
already which were developed from so-called 'peaceful' nuclear power
plant technology. Pakistan is known to be close to developing nuclear
weapons, and their plant has been bought surreptitiously upon the open
world market. Israel is publicly strongly believed to have produced
several nuclear weapons, as has also South Africa. However, nuclear
power plants do not provide all the technology necessary for weapons
of the traditional type and only certain types produce plutonium which
is a potential 'nuclear weapon' in itself, if of unconventional sort,
being extremely poisonous and easy to spread. Therefore the tenability
of P1 is not 100%. Had the phrase 'can under certain conditions' been
included, it would have been completely tenable in my judgement.
The tenability of P1 makes the truth of 10 highly likely, therefore
the argument is highly relevant to the issue.
P2 is contested by c1P2, which is again contested by c1c1P2. This latter
argument is highly tenable in my opinion as there are already recorded
and confirmed cases of theft of fissionable products from nuclear power
plants, chiefly one in U.K. in 1982 where a researcher stole 1 lb. of
plutonium so as to prove that the security forces were fallible at a
nuclear power station. Therefore I regard P2 as tenable and this does
increase world insecurity, making it also highly relevant.
C1 appears to argue that 'expert scientists' would never stoop to developing
nuclear weapons, which is provenly untrue. In this case it makes little
difference whether they own the technology or its products, so c1C1
has little relevance, though high tenability. Nuclear technology is
no longer completely controlled by expert scientists in the security
sense, which further weakens C1. If 'controlled' were interpreted as
'economically controlled', which is unlikely in the context, c1C1 would
then appear much more relevant and would weaken C1 yet further.
All in all, I regard C1 as
untenable, therefore also irrelevant to the issue.
Concerning the relative strength of arguments, therefore I find two
strong main arguments supporting the statement "World security
is threatened by nuclear power plants."
The conclusion was here reached on the basis of the explicit arguments
plus additional facts introduced when evaluating their tenability and
relevance. Optimally such facts should be included in the explicit arguments
of the survey. However, as all arguments end somewhere and all relevant
facts cannot be enumerated that the mind can review, Judgements of tenability
will invariably depend upon the experience and knowledge of the one
who judges.
Prescriptive 'arguments'
A prescriptive statement
does not constitute a logical argument because its function or purpose
is to be emotive (i.e. to persuade) and is not cognitive.
To argue for or against a value (as expressed in a prescriptive issue-statement)
by forwarding another value does not make an explicit and rational
argument, from the viewpoint of logic and science. This view is strictly
'rationalist' because it admits no value judgements in a purely reasoning
process, insisting on cognitive arguments formulated in descriptive
statements (and not in prescriptive statements). It is rationalist in
that it sets reason above emotion. In many cultures, however, this sort
of rationalism is rejected and values are frequently therefore forwarded
as support for and against issues of a normative sort. For example,
consider this:-
I0 "One ought to believe in God"
P1 "Yes. Because not to do so is morally wrong"
p1P1 "And this leads to belief in justification for any
inhuman acts"
P1 is clearly a prescriptive
statement and one which many would accept as a good argument for I0.
Here, however it is not formulated as a logical or empirical ground
for I0, so it must be regarded as irrelevant to I0. The sub-argument
p1P1, however, makes explicit what is thought to be one consequence
of morally wrongful non-belief in God. So p1P1 could be tested as to
its tenability and therefore could stand as a rational ground for I0.
It could be re-labeled P1 instead of as P1 above, which latter is rejected
from any ordered survey. Whether p1P1 (now P1) is a strong or tenable
argument is another question. At least it puts forward a view that is
testable in principle, though doubtless very difficult to test in practice.
It assumes also that the term 'inhuman' is not normative, which is open
to question. Further definition of the term 'inhuman' would be required
before any test would be practically feasible. For example, 'inhuman
acts' could be defined as 'acts contrary to the Geneva Contention of
1948's Declaration of Human Rights. Even then, conclusive testing of
the tenability of p1P1 would be highly difficult and probably most controversial.
Sub-arguments concerning relevance or tenability
When sub-arguments are forwarded
they will tend to support or weaken the main argument. This can be achieved
in two distinct ways, either by strengthening/weakening the main argument's
tenability, or by strengthening/weakening its relevance to the issue-statement.
For example:-
I0 "One ought to demonstrate against the nuclear arms race".
P1 "This will increase the likelihood that leaders of nuclear
nations will negotiate for nuclear disarmament in good faith, stopping
the arms race"
c1P1 "No. Leaders of Warsaw Pact countries will not be influenced
by demonstrations".
c1P1 is an argument against
the tenability of the next argument of higher order. If c1P1 is judged
tenable, it will weaken the tenability of P1. This makes it a relevant
argument against P1 (see definition of relevance for descriptive issue-statements.
P1 has now become, for all intents, a descriptive issue-statement in
relation to c1P1 (which is like a first-order argument against it now).
Yet consider the following arguments:
c2P1 "No. Nuclear disarmament negotiations are never influenced
by demonstrations, only by economic-military strategic considerations"
p1P1 "Yes. Demonstrations which express very strong public opinions
eventually influence the leaders of States."
Both of the above arguments refer to the relevance of P1 as an argument for I0. Of course, c1P1 is against P1, an argument attempting to show that P1 has limited relevance to I0, while p1P1 attempts to show that P1 does have relevance to I0. Which is strongest depends upon the tenability of c1P1 and p1P1 (as well as any other arguments that might be included which concern the relevance of P1 to I0).
The process of evaluation
of any main argument requires, therefore, that all of the sub-arguments
be evaluated - starting with those of the lowest order and working gradually
'upwards' towards the main argument at the top. Each sub-argument is
evaluated for its tenability and its relevance to the next argument
(in ascending order). It is important to distinguish whether a sub-argument
relates to the tenability or the relevance of the argument above it.
When such judgements have been made, an overall judgement of the tenability
and relevance of the main argument can be made. This is a rule-of-thumb
judgement in most cases of arguments for issues of a broad or general
nature and it decides the strength of the argument. This argument
will then be subsequently compared with other arguments, both pro- and
contra- arguments of the 1'st order so that a conclusion as to whether
the issue is supported or weakened by the arguments available can be
made. In some cases the arguments for and against may balance one another
so that a conclusion cannot be reached, even on the strength of available
evidence. Again, where broad issues are involved, it will seldom be
possible to marshall all the arguments of importance, especially not
all possible relevant and tenable sub-arguments. As said, all arguments
end somewhere.
Prescriptive issue-statements
Prescriptive issue-statements,
which express a norm and advocate action, require somewhat different
treatment. When the issue-statement expresses a norm (is prescriptive)
the arguments relevant to it may often also be prescriptive, including
value-statements and tenets of belief. These can invariably be expressed
as descriptive statements instead, which helps to clarify then and make
the evaluation of their tenability possible (for prescriptive statements
cannot be true or false, by definition). Relevance is also judged in
a different way for prescriptive issues.
When forwarding arguments for or against a prescriptive issue-statement
it will be most convenient to formulate them so that they express a
consequence of the state of affairs in the issue-statement becoming
realised. We shall call such types of argument 'consequence arguments'.
One asks: "What would be the consequences of 10 being realised?"
The answer should be a descriptive statement. As an example consider
the following consequence argument for I1 (below):-
Prescriptive issue-statement:
I0 'Observe human rights everywhere'. This is not very precise,
therefore, to clarify the issue it could be re-stated more precisely
as:
I1 'The governments of all nations ought to observe the articles
of the 1948 United Nations' Declaration of Human Rights'
P1 'Then political oppression would cease'.
The 'then' expresses that
the argument is a consequence of the realisation of I0. Had the argument
been expressed as a norm, it might have been:
P1 'because political oppression ought to be brought to an end'.
This prescriptive statement cannot be regarded as tenable or untenable,
hence the consequence argument form instead.
Consider a second-order argument against P1 and the issue-statement:
c1P1 'but political oppression not covered by the articles of
the 1948 Declaration could still occur'.
This evidently, if tenable, reduces the tenability of P1 and weakens
the argument. As to the relevance of P1 one must ask 'Is it likely that
political oppression would cease as a consequence of the governments
of all nations observing the articles of the United Nations' Declaration
of Human Rights?' If so, the argument can be relevant, if doubtful the
argument may still be relevant but, if not, the argument is most unlikely
to be relevant. The final test of relevance is whether the judge of
the argument considers it to predict a good or an ill. If one considers
it good that political oppression should cease, or also if one regards
it as ill, the argument is relevant. If neither, then it is irrelevant.
Sometimes an argument that is relevant to a prescriptive issue-statement
will be virtually impossible to re-formulate as a consequence argument
without losing the clarity and force of the argument. Consider:-
I0 "One ought to demonstrate so as to reduce inflation"
and the argument against this, pure and simple, that
C1 "demonstration is an entirely ineffective method of achieving
reduced inflation".
It would be somewhat absurd to try to formulate this as a consequence
argument, though it could be written alternatively as follows, perhaps:-
C1 "then one would be using an entirely ineffective method
of achieving
reduced inflation".
In this case, the argument amounts to a rejection of the issue itself, as if to say 'the issue-statement is so absurd as to be worthless for discussion'. This is frequently a problem with prescriptive issues. Those who do not consider the subject of the issue to be important, who do not assert the value concerned, nor its antithesis, may forward a rational ground why the issue itself is inconsequential. This amounts to rejecting an issue as irrelevant to fruitful discussion or research.
In some respects an issue is much like an hypothesis, the grounds for or against which one wishes to summarise and evaluate. A fruitful hypothesis is like a fruitful issue. Both can be tested by some means and both will lead to improvement in our knowledge if the ensuing debate or investigation helps to weaken or strengthen the statement in question.
Since prescriptive issue-statements
express norms (i.e. are often called 'normative statements') they usually
forward a value (or counter-value). The qualifier 'usually' is employed
here since, as has' been shown, a statement with a prescriptive form
can nonetheless have a descriptive function in reality (as contrariwise
for descriptive statements). Those prescriptive issue-statements which
also have a normative function (despite the actual wording) - such as
"One ought not kill other human beings" may have been derived
from arguments in the first place. Or else - as is most likely in the
case of the present example (if taken to be an appropriate interpretation
of one of the 10 commandments from the Book of Moses) - it has been
put forward as a norm according to which arguments can be ordered after
interpreting and applying the norm. In other words, there is an intimate
or internal relationship between any issue-statement and the arguments
that it will organise, or - in the opposite direction - between the
data and viewpoints which, when considered together, give rise to a
normative statement. This two-way relationship is comparable to that
between regarding a system of statements as a deductive or as an inductive
system, as will be considered in the next part of this book.
Some practical advice
on making ordered surveys
l) The issue-statement must be clear and concise. The
principles of efficient communication should be followed in formulating
the issue-expression. Obscure, insufficiently-precise and inappropriate
terms generally must be avoided. Where the issue-statement is insufficiently-precise,
the result will usually be that two dr more distinct debates will take
place at the sane time on the basis of two or more likely interpretations
of the issue-statement. This problem can be aided by formulating an
antithesis to the issue statement, which thereby helps narrow the interpretations
of it. For example:-10 "I ought to stop smoking completely"
can have as an antithesis either;- Antithesis; "I ought to continue
smoking as usual" or:- Antithesis: "I ought to continue smoking,
but reduce consumption to half". Both these antitheses cannot be
used at once, for the arguments that will be ordered under 10 will alter
depending upon which antithesis applies.
2) Arguments must
be clear and concise. The most common faults in forming arguments
tend to be vagueness, inexplicitness and compounding different arguments
together into one.
A vague argument will contain terms that are not sufficiently precise
to allow ordering of the argument (whether pro- or contra-, whether
first or second order etc.). Insufficiently explicit statements fail
to be clear how the argument is related to the issue or to arguments
of a higher order, so these must be rethought and reformulated. Compounded
arguments can usually be separated into separate arguments without much
difficulty.
Examples:-
Arguments for and against I0 "I ought to stop smoking"
P1 'because my health is a problem.'
This argument is vague, relatively
imprecise. What aspect of health? How is it related to smoking? One
may try to make it more explicit and clear as:-
P1 'because then my general health would improve due to less congestion
of the lungs, improved circulation of the blood and a more positive
outlook.' However, this argument compounds three grounds into one. It
should be reformulated as three separate arguments (P1, P2 and P3 or
else as P1 with supporting p1P1, p2p1 and p3Pl).
Only when an argument is clear, concise and thus sufficiently precise
can its tenability and relevance be evaluated. In general, the more
precise, the more reliable evaluations of tenability and relevance are
possible. This strengthens the arguments and improves the overall impact
of a survey.
SAMPLE OF A BRIEF ORDERED SURVEY TO INDICATE
A METHOD IN EVALUATING THE ARGUMENTS
The following issue-statement (I0)expresses a view
forwarded by U.S. Government agencies:
I0 The neutron bomb ought
to be manufactured in the interests of world peace. To make the issue adequately explicit a more
precise statement is suggested:- I1 The neutron bomb ought to be manufactured by the U.S. in the interests of world peace |
This issue-statement is prescriptive. The first-order arguments will thus be set up as consequences of the manufacture of the neutron bomb |
PRO- arguments |
CONTRA-arguments |
P1 then the Russians would be
more eager to agree to nuclear disarmament c1P1 but experience shows this to be most unlikely P2 then N.A.T.O. forces would have a stronger deterrent to war. c1P2 but N.A.T.O. forces already have enough atomic weaponry to annihilate humanity c1c1P2 but deterrence is even stronger when based on fear of horrible sufferings from radiation illnesses. c1c1c1P2 but widespread fear is not conducive to world peace. |
C1 then the Russians would soon produce
the neutron bomb too.
|
EXERCISES (ORDERED SURVEYS)
1) A: Poor countries
ought to give modern technological expertise a leading role in their
development, because they will be more capable of surviving world economic
competition.
B: They will not, for the profits are always mostly taken abroad by
the foreign investors who finance such technology.
A: But not if poor countries control the investors through taxation.
B: That is seldom effective against big companies. Technological development
destroys the national cultures of peoples, it creates mass unemployment
for the poorest and eventually brings the same economic problem that
Western countries are facing today.
A: But Western countries are not poor countries.
a) Order the above discussion
in the form of a logically-consistent argument survey, clearly indicating
which are pro- and which contra-arguments, and of what order you consider
them to be. Give reasons.
b) Formulate one first-order argument of your own, either pro- or contra-,
and then evaluate the tenability and relevance of each of the first-order
arguments, explaining how you do this.
2) Consider the following text:-
'The study of the history of philosophy is of educational value to university
students today: The study has been criticised, however, for dealing
almost only with what past thinkers have thought, often mistakenly.
This neglects the fact that the ideas and language in important areas
of society are the result of those of previous thinkers'.
a) Order the above text in an ordered argument survey, clearly indicating
which of the above statements is the issue-statement and which can be
ordered as arguments for and against it.
b) State one argument of your own either for or against the issue-statement.
c) State your evaluation of the tenability and relevance and logical
consistency of each of the arguments, explaining how such evaluations
are made.
3) Consider the following discussion between two persons, A and
B:-
A: People should never use terror to achieve their purposes.
B: But terrorism often achieves results, such as awakening the world
to the sufferings of an oppressed people.
A: That may be true, but use of terror also often causes its victims
to repay it with use of terror.
a) Set the above discussion
in an ordered argument survey, clearly indicating which of the above
statements is the issue-statement and which are arguments for or against
it.
b) Explain what is meant by the tenability of arguments for or against
a prescriptive issue-statement. What is your evaluation of the tenability
of the above arguments?
c) Explain what is meant by the relevance of arguments for or against
a prescriptive issue-statement. What is your evaluation of the relevance
of the above arguments?